Many respond to Singer’s pond analogy by suggesting that we have unusually stringent positive duties to aid in emergencies, that do not carry over to everyday aid. In this post, I’ll argue against this view by (1) showing why a recently-advanced theoretical basis for this view, the “informal-insurance model”, fails; and (2) undermining the intuition that it would be wrong to pass by the drowning child in order to indirectly save multiple other children.
The Informal-Insurance Model
Common sense would like to combine a minimal view of our everyday obligations with ambitious positive obligations to assist in cases of proximate emergency (like a child drowning right before your eyes). The difficulty for this view is to provide it with a principled basis. Why should emergency deaths be treated as inherently more important than equally preventable deaths from ongoing causes?
Sterri and Moen propose to explain this in terms of an "Informal-Insurance Model". Their basic idea is that emergency ethics can be understood as a mutually-beneficial compact amongst all in the moral community to informally insure each other against rare, unexpected risks of grave harm. That is, we undertake to help others out in emergency situations, on the understanding that they would do the same for us. Since emergencies are rare, the comfortably-off can agree to participate in such a scheme without expecting to be bled dry by all the world's needs. And since emergency situations can befall anyone, it is in their enlightened self-interest to do so. We are all better off informally insuring each other against disaster in this way, than if we all were left to fend for ourselves.
This line of argument faces two significant problems, common to efforts to ground ethics in “enlightened” self-interest. Firstly, the underlying logic of mutual benefit excludes from the moral community not just the global poor but also those nearby (including infants, non-human animals, and the severely disabled) who are not in a position to reciprocate. But surely you still ought to rescue a drowning paraplegic, for example, even if he could not do the same for you.
The second problem is that even when the informal insurance model gets the right result (requiring that you help), it does so for the wrong reasons. It implies that you should help for the sake of playing your part in a co-operative scheme of mutual benefit, which doesn't seem remotely the right reason to save a child from drowning.
To see this, imagine extending the logic of the informal insurance model to a society including water-phobic robots who just want to collect paperclips but occasionally drop them in puddles. In order to secure the assistance of the robots in helping to free us from getting our feet caught on railroad tracks (or other non-water-related emergencies), we might reciprocate by rescuing their lost paperclips from puddles. If the informal insurance account of emergency ethics were correct, then your moral reason to save a drowning child would be of exactly the same kind as your reason to "save" a paperclip from a puddle in the imagined scenario. But this is clearly wrong. We have moral reasons to save lives and avert great harms for the sake of the affected individuals. These moral reasons are distinct from (and more important than) our reasons to participate in mutual-benefit schemes.
Passing by the Pond
The imperative to save drowning children can (ironically enough) be used against effective altruism. Just suppose that you’re on your way to donate enough to save multiple lives, but then come across a drowning child who you can only save at the cost of ruining the money you were about to donate. Sure seems like you ought to save the drowning child, despite the inefficiency!
My standard response to this is to see it as revealing more about psychology than morality. We probably can’t help but massively over-weight salient interests, and it doesn’t get any more salient than a child drowning right before your eyes. Who knows who you would’ve saved otherwise, by contrast. There’s little chance they’ll haunt your nightmares, the way that the visible child might if you simply watched them drown. Anyone who doesn’t react this way, we’d suspect of being inhumanly callous. Maybe they did the best thing on this occasion (saving multiple lives), but if they were willing to watch a child drown they surely lack the empathy and person-directed moral concern that seems essential to being a decent person. Most people probably wouldn’t have a lot of trust in such a person to act well in other situations.
Maybe these psychological facts suffice to explain our distaste for letting indirect aid trump the drowning child’s interests, without needing to posit that there’s really any stronger moral reasons to prioritize the nearby child. But it’s still an awkward intuition to grapple with. So I wonder if we might do more to undermine it.
Here’s a thought. Suppose you knew there were four drowning children, each in different nearby locations. You could directly save any one of them, though the others would drown in the meantime. But there’s an alternative. The different locations are linked up in such a way that, upon reaching any one of the four locations, the other three will receive a temporary boost of buoyancy that would give you time to enlist the aid of emergency services to save the other three. But you only have time to do this if you do not save the one who is (by then) right in front of you. And this one will drown before the emergency services arrive. What should you do?
Before you set out, it seems pretty clear to me that you should pre-commit to enlisting emergency services, whichever pond you happen to reach first. Without knowing which route you plan to take, it’s obviously in the expected best interests of the four for you to do what will save 3/4 rather than 1/4 of them. They would all agree to that beforehand, if they could. So it would be special pleading for the unlucky one to subsequently demand that you change your mind and save only them after all, just because they’re the one that ends up in your line of sight once the plan is underway.
So it’s not universally true that you’re morally required to save the one right before your eyes rather than indirectly saving several (when you cannot do both). Moreover, it’s hard to see why the mere fact that the other needy children were comparably near to your starting position should carry any moral weight, in setting this apart from a case where you save distant lives via donating to charity. The real significance of the set-up, it seems to me, lies just in making the others’ needs comparably salient (ex ante) to the one you end up seeing. This helps us to overcome a distorting effect that otherwise biases our moral reasoning in such cases. So the conclusion I’m inclined to draw from this case is more general: that you’re never really required to save the one right before your eyes rather than indirectly saving several.
Conclusion
Putting this all together, I reject the claim that “emergency ethics” warrants different fundamental norms than “everyday ethics” when comparably grave interests are at stake. Put another way, we should see ongoing harms to distant others as every bit the moral emergency that we perceive unusual nearby harms to be.
Richard Yetter Chappelle
I see your argument and understand the principles they are based in, however, it raises some difficulties for me. I am not a philosopher, or academic, so go easy on me. I also happen to believe your argument is from the heart, and trying to convince the reader that the troubles far from us deserve more attention than we give them.😉
In the emergent situation, how could any moral or ethical person make the SURE decision that their actions for the "others" would be completed. The person at the trolley switch could be hit by a bus before their act of charity is completed.
Another way to frame your argument is the example of high military command, where the sacrifice of few, to achieve a strategic good, is considered acceptable. This example has been discussed, by military folk since the beginning of warfare.
Your conclusion is in opposition to another commonly practiced emergency ethics skill, triage. Simply put, the nearby harms are the ones we have the highest probability of stopping. We, as human beings must address the harms nearest to us in order to be able to address the next closest harm. The alternative is to spread the resources of rescue to a point where they become ineffective. On a personal level, I cant maintain my own sanity if I try to right ALL of the wrongs, I have to keep focused on the problems I can affect.
As a military, and first responder type person, I try to do both, even when the odds are too long to contemplate. I train my subordinates to attempt the same. I believe your argument fails the real world test for another reason. Those of us on the front lines believe in luck, angels, and the impossible chance. We won't stop fighting for the lives of all four children in the water as long as hope remains.
Very Respectfully,
James Anderson
Chief Petty Officer
United States Coast Guard
Framing non-emergency ethics as everyday ethics is misleading. Non emergency situations are not everyday or regular or easy. They require an even higher duty to act in a way that prevents rather than awaits emergency. The challenge is implementing this structurally and without added burdens in addition to daily missions to procure shelter, food, and company. Work should in virtue of itself prevent disaster not await it. Only in a world where our work awaits disaster do we need anything like effective altruism to clean up the mess.
In this way, emergency ethics aren’t the special situation, but rather normal reactions to improbable events: of course you save someone in trouble whether the baby or a community suffering from a tsunami across the pond. Instead some of the brightest minds today are optimizing a relatively minuscule pool of funds to support institutionalized, government approved, status quo maintaining entities rather than building a better world.