Distinguish practical norms from the theoretical question of what justifies them.
Hypothesis: many are drawn to deontology as a result of conflating these two. People sensibly want to endorse good practical norms like Rɪɢʜᴛs (Don’t violate rights, even if you think it’s for the best). And they assume that this commits them to a deontological theory of why that’s a good norm. But that assumption is mistaken. No such theoretical commitment is required.
After explaining why this is so, I’ll introduce a conceptually simple alternative—deontic fictionalism—for those who find two-level consequentialism hard to fathom.
Background: Norm content vs justification
The distinction between a theory’s criterion (or moral goals) and its recommended decision procedure is central to consequentialism. But others don’t always realize this.1 Much confusion in moral theory stems from people conflating the practical question of whether to endorse a norm against X with the theoretical question of whether agents have non-instrumental reason to avoid doing X. These are different questions!
Utilitarians and moderate deontologists alike agree that (i) you shouldn’t go around carving people up for their organs, and (ii) there are conceivable exceptions to this rule. There’s no surface-level practical difference in this respect.2 The difference is not in whether it’s wrong to kill, but why.
Consider again the norm Rɪɢʜᴛs (Don’t violate rights, even if you think it’s for the best).
Rɪɢʜᴛs is an excellent practical norm! I endorse it wholeheartedly. (One can imagine exceptions to it, of course, as any moderate deontologist will agree; but that doesn’t undermine its status as a good norm, well worth inculcating in ourselves and others.)
Now, I think the justification for Rɪɢʜᴛs is ultimately instrumental: that respecting rights seems likely to result in better actions, yielding better outcomes, than would disregarding them. I think that’s a better justification than what deontologists offer, which is why I reject deontology. The dispute between the theories is not so much about what norms to embrace, but why.
People sometimes get confused at this point, since Rɪɢʜᴛs doesn’t look, on its face, like a “utilitarian” norm or decision procedure. The content of the norm makes no approving references to promoting value. But that’s fine, because moral theories aren’t accounts of what norms to embrace. They’re accounts of fundamental (non-instrumental) reasons (including reasons to embrace some norms over others). Utilitarianism, in particular, fundamentally tells us to promote value. So if embracing Rɪɢʜᴛs promotes value, then utilitarianism straightforwardly implies that we should embrace Rɪɢʜᴛs.
Moreover, this isn’t even “self-effacing” (which is something else that people often seem to get confused about).3 Acting well is compatible with accurately appreciating that the reasons to embrace Rɪɢʜᴛs are instrumental rather than non-instrumental.4 So we can perfectly well maintain a utilitarian perspective on the world, and deliberately follow utilitarian reasons—aiming to maximize expected value—while embracing Rɪɢʜᴛs. This is all perfectly coherent, so long as we appreciate that following Rɪɢʜᴛs has higher expected value than blindly following naïve calculations. Utilitarian reasons then direct us to let Rɪɢʜᴛs constrain our actions. (And no, this still isn’t rule utilitarianism.)
Deontic Fictionalism
Some Christian philosophers are religious fictionalists: granting that their religion isn’t literally true, but embracing its rituals and practices nonetheless. When they affirm their church’s dogmas, there’s an implicit “according to the fiction” qualifier attached. They don’t mean this in a dismissive way, though. They think it’s a good and worthwhile pretense to engage in, perhaps for social or emotional reasons.
It’s interesting to consider whether some who are initially drawn to “commonsense” deontology might be satisfied with deontic fictionalism: granting that the theoretical claims of deontology are misguided, but endorsing the practical norms. If it makes it easier for them to maintain motivation, then engaging in deontological pretense—behaving as if the theory were true—might turn out to be good and worthwhile. That’s something you can do without getting stuck with deontology’s theoretical baggage.
On this picture, one can even use moral language like “right” and “wrong” in a way that tracks deontological verdicts: “It’s wrong to push the guy in front of the trolley, even if it would save more lives.” But there’s an implicit “according to the fiction of deontology” qualifier attached. You’re well aware that, in principle, there’s always most reason to do what’s best, and to hope for the best outcome. But you’re now using moral language to do something other than relate the reasons-facts. Maybe you’re instead using it to express support for practical norms like Rɪɢʜᴛs. Indeed, given how poorly others mark the distinctions explained in this post, it may even be that this non-literal mode of moral communication is less misleading for many audiences than the alternative of affirming your literal theoretical beliefs (which they might misinterpret as support for naïve utilitarian practical norms).
Three Options
Compare three different ways one might respond to the instrumental reasons to embrace Rɪɢʜᴛs and related practical norms:
(1) Prudent (two-level) consequentialism, where one accepts Rɪɢʜᴛs and related norms as instrumentally good heuristics, while denying both (i) that these norms specify non-instrumental reasons, and (ii) that such non-instrumental reasons are necessary to justify following the norms.
(2) Deontic fictionalism, where one accepts Rɪɢʜᴛs and related norms due to endorsing (on instrumental grounds) behaving as if deontology5 were true, without any commitment to the literal truth of deontological theory.
(3) Deontology (via self-effacing consequentialism), where instrumental reasons motivate one to (somehow) believe that deontology is true—or to convince others to believe it.
I personally think #1 is the ideal way to go. But if some find it difficult to grasp, option #2 may prove a conceptually simpler alternative that still maintains epistemic integrity (for those who agree that the theoretical case for consequentialism is strong).
Given these alternatives, it doesn’t seem plausible to me that there’s any practical reason to prefer #3. Whenever people suggest practical reasons to embrace deontological moral theories, one may counter with deontic fictionalism instead. (And when they’re ready to take off the training wheels, they can shift to prudent consequentialism: dropping the pretense entirely while keeping on following good norms like Rɪɢʜᴛs, just for the actually-right reasons.)
See, e.g., post-FTX anti-utilitarian takes on philosophy twitter, as represented in meme form here.
One can carefully engineer hypothetical cases to pry the two views apart. But even then, I argued, utilitarians will typically see grounds to criticize the agent (e.g. for recklessness) even if they approve of the act in retrospect, given that it turned out for the best. And, seriously, what kind of person doesn’t approve of things turning out for the best? Not a good one, that’s for sure.
It’s always possible for a decent moral view to be self-effacing, because having true beliefs isn’t the most important thing in the world. If an evil demon said “Agree to moral brainwashing or I’ll torture everyone for eternity,” then you’d obviously better agree to the brainwashing. But that’s not what’s going on here. Absent evil demons, we don’t need false moral beliefs.
Sometimes people say things which seem to imply that instrumental reasons don’t count. (“Utilitarians have no in principle objection to slavery!” What, you mean the suffering of the slaves is not enough? “But it could in principle be outweighed by other considerations!” That’s true of moderate deontologists, too. “Well, okay, but it just makes all the difference if some of the outweighed reasons were non-instrumental…” Why? I’m starting to worry that you’re really not giving enough weight to the suffering of the slaves…) So it’s maybe worth being explicit at this point that all this talk of “instrumental reasons” is shorthand for the most obviously important reasons that there are, namely those to save and improve lives.
Ideally, in a more beneficentric form than one usually finds in the wild.
Can you comment on the distinction between
1. Behaving as if deontology is true, on the object level: following RIGHTS and related norms
2. Behaving as if deontology is true, on the meta level: saying the kinds of things a deontologist would say (things like "we have non-instrumental reasons to follow RIGHTS")
My guess is you mean for deontic fictionalism to refer to just (1)?
I agree with the view you present here, but I think the best arguments in favour of self-effacing consequentialism are psychological and sociological, not directly philosophical. Are we (individually or collectively) capable of adhering to a norm if we regard it as only instrumental? Are we capable of behaving _as if_ a theory is true, without believing in it?
I think arguments along these lines can be overstated, but they're at least not crazy, and I think to be fully convincing you have to address to what extent our (again, individually or collectively) capacity to be "deontic fictionalists" is a real practical difficulty to be overcome.
Moreover, I think you rightly emphasize deontic fictionalism as a sort of middle-ground position, ("training wheels") that is a little unstable--but for people who worry that real prudent two-level consequentialism is too hard to maintain (if we know the norms are instrumental, it will always be easy to find instrumental reasons to discard them in particular cases), that very instability is a problem. If position 1 isn't psychologically or socially feasible, and if position 2 is just the training wheels version of 1, then that strengthens the case for 3.